SSS Yet To Be Done.
Subjectivation
The concept of subjectivation owes its attractiveness to a current epistemic and societal problematic: the drifting apart of communities of knowledge and the resulting crisis of truth and justice. The dominant reaction to this crisis is a withdrawal to scientism and technocracy, reinforcing divisions between subject and object, researcher and ‘subject’, pushing back the dangerous voice of the ‘masses’. Our alternative approach is to study contexts and institutions of subjection, to observe how subjects of rights emerge, and to identify emancipatory moments in processes of subject formation. Subjectivation research aims to promote a vocabulary and a set of methods, which allows members of society – including researchers – to negotiate structural constraints and to distribute agency broadly within societies. Subjectivation research can contribute to the study of ‘social embeddedness of agency’ through an understanding of relationality: the mutual stabilisation of subject-producing societies and society-producing subjects through shaping their relation in processes of longue durée. The subject is a relational entity (Donati & Archer 2015): its individuation relies on offers of relationship, and is never complete. This individuation is prone to accidents, which consist of changes in relations, new relations, and the finitude of relations. The struggles of subjects-in-relations vis-à-vis the law, social and symbolic order, institutional realizations, and the collective or networked attainment of rights should become focal points for further studies. By analyzing the longue durée of social and symbolic orders and by confronting these with social action, we observe how subjects change in structure and how structure changes in regard to subjects’ actions. It is important to note that the issue of subjection (Ger. Unterwerfung, Fr. assujettisement) is of limited importance – it describes the limits of subjectivation in terms of the attainments of rights. Also, asking about subjectivation in terms of post-Kantian, phenomenological subjectivity may help to show how actors represent social reality and think beyond it, but it alone does not necessarily lead to the issue of the subject of rights. Both subjection and subjectivity are terms we need to describe the limits of and presuppositions for the attainment of rights-generating agency, since neo-Kantian or Foucauldian discourse theory are in themselves little helpful in describing the participatory vicissitudes of the struggles of talking back (hooks 1989) to authorities. These are struggles for the right to ‘subjectivate ourselves’, shifting the boundaries between us, them, and I.
https://practicaltheorist.wordpress.com/2014/05/24/structure-and-agency/
Structure and Agency
Christopher Powell / May 24, 2014
I feel that I’ve never understood what the word ‘agency’ is supposed to mean.
In social science it commonly appears as the opposite term of ‘structure’ as in the phrase ‘structure vs. agency‘. This duality connotes the supposed opposition between social forces and individual autonomy in causing the actions of human beings.
I have no trouble understanding how human action is socially caused, i.e. the ‘structure’ side of the duality. But I cannot even imagine what the other side of the equation is supposed to refer to.
Let me explain:
Assume an imaginary world in which all human beings have the same motivations and the same perceptions. For the sake of simplicity let’s assume also that the world is objectively real and that people perceive it objectively.
In this world, human action would be caused entirely by the availability of opportunities for people to realize their motivations.
In this world, if there were no probability or chaos then understanding human nature and knowing objective reality would enable us to predict human action with perfect accuracy. We would know what a given person or any number of people would do next on the basis of what opportunities were available to them. Economists and rational choice theorists build abstract models aimed at precisely this kind of prediction. Of course, they tend to base their models only on instrumentally rational motivations, i.e. motivations for personal gain defined in some objective, quantifiable way. But even without those limiting assumptions, the principle would still hold that, in our imagined world of universal fixed motivations and perceptions, knowledge of human and nonhuman nature would allow us to explain human action as a function of the opportunities available for people to realize their motives.
In other words, we could explain human action entirely by studying the distribution and movement of opportunities.
Let me use the word ‘structure’ to refer to this distribution and movement. In particular, let me shed the notion that ‘structure’ refers to something fixed and static, like the structure of a building; let us use the word ‘structure’ to embrace a wide range of concepts of emergent order, including relation, process, figuration, system, and so on.
To the extent that opportunities are produced by human interaction, and not simply by nonhuman nature alone, then opportunity structures are social structures.
To sum up: if human motivations were constant and universal, and if the opportunity structure were entirely a product of human interaction, then all variation in human action would be determined by social structures.
Let me clear up a few misconceptions that might arise:
- The causal importance of social structure in this model has nothing to do with political oppression or liberty; i.e. ‘structure vs. agency’ does not map onto ‘authoritarianism vs freedom’. The actions of a person who has all the freedoms of the modern white male heteronormative bourgeois subject are still just as socially structured as those of a slave or a prisoner in a concentration camp.
- Similarly, the causal importance of social structure in this scenario has nothing to do with the extent to which people exercise individual creativity or intelligence in deciding their actions. This is because we are assuming (for the sake of illustration) that all people have basically the same cognitive facilities, so that variations in how they use those cognitive facilities are caused by variations in their social situation.
- Social causality is not the same as societal causality. Social structure exist on any level of scale from the global to fleeting interactions between two people. The actions of a person who violates societal norms because the local structure of opportunities makes doing so the more effective path to realizing their motives are, in this model, just as socially determined as those of a normative conformist. In the former case, they are caused by local social structures (maybe even features particular to one interaction between two people) which happen to conflict with more dominant or widely distributed social structures.
Furthermore, as far as I can tell, complicating this model by introducing confusion or ignorance into people’s knowledge of the opportunities available to them, or by making the consequences of action dependent on chance (probability) or chaotic (stochastic) causality does not modify the conclusion: as long as human nature is constant, then variations in human action must be explainable by variations in the structure and system of opportunities for the realization of people’s motives.
* * *
Obviously this account of human action as completely determined by social structure depends on highly artificial and unrealistic assumptions. I’ve made these assumptions to clarify what I mean by social structure, not because I think they obtain. So let’s open things back up.
As soon as we allow that people’s motives vary, as they obviously do in real life, things get considerably more complicated. Then we must ask: where do motives come from? What causes people to have the motives they do?
From the perspective of a naturalistic social science – that is, an investigation that refuses to invoke the soul or any other theological or metaphysical notions – any explanation for human motivation must lie in one or more domains of the natural universe. Broadly, these can include physiological factors (genetics, hormones, etc.), psychological factors (cognitive dispositions, concepts, the unconscious, etc.), social factors (relationships, institutions, norms, etc.), and ecological factors (the living and inanimate nonhumans to which people relate) — recognizing that these three domains overlap considerably. Explanation in any of these domains necessarily invokes some concepts of structure.
Whether my motives arise from my physical environment, biology, my cognition, or my social relations, or some complex interaction of all four, a scientific explanation of my actions necessarily explains my motives in terms of some combination of structures.
This is still the case even I observe that I act reflexively on myself (e.g. through meditation or therapy or whatever) to change my own motivations. I am still acting out a motivation to change my motivations, and that motivation came from somewhere.
If my actions are caused by my motivations relative to my opportunities, and my motivations themselves are caused by some combination of ecological, biophysical, psychological, and social structures (or, more precisely, my motives are themselves physical, psychological, and social structures simultaneously), then there seems to be no meaningful sense in which my actions are ‘self-determined’ for the purposes of scientific explanation. ‘Agency’ defined as ‘self-determination’ seems
So … what is agency supposed to be? What is left over?
(Addendum for system theorists: is ‘agency’ just that portion of my action which is determined by the personality system as distinct from the social or cultural systems? Is that really all that the word is supposed to mean?)
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Structure_and_agency
In the social sciences there is a standing debate over the primacy of structure or agency in shaping human behaviour. Structure is the recurrent patterned arrangements which influence or limit the choices and opportunities available. Agency is the capacity of individuals to act independently and to make their own free choices. The structure versus agency debate may be understood as an issue of socialization against autonomy in determining whether an individual acts as a free agent or in a manner dictated by social structure.
Structure, socialization and autonomy
The debate over the primacy of structure or of agency relates to an issue at the heart of both classical and contemporary sociological theory: the question of social ontology: "What is the social world made of?" "What is a cause of the social world, and what is an effect?" "Do social structures determine an individual's behaviour or does human agency?"
Structural functionalists such as Émile Durkheim see structure and hierarchy as essential in establishing the very existence of society. Theorists such as Karl Marx, by contrast, emphasize that the social structure can act to the detriment of the majority of individuals in a society. In both these instances "structure" may refer to something both material (or "economic") and cultural (i.e. related to norms, customs, traditions and ideologies).
Some theorists put forward that what we know as our social existence is largely determined by the overall structure of society. The perceived agency of individuals can also mostly be explained by the operation of this structure. Theoretical systems aligned with this view include:
All of these schools in this context can be seen as forms of holism – the notion that "the whole is greater than the sum of its parts".
On the other hand, other theorists stress the capacity of individual "agents" to construct and reconstruct their worlds. In this sense the individual can be viewed as more influential than the system. Theoretical systems aligned with this view include:
Lastly, a third option, taken by many modern social theorists, attempts to find a point of balance between the two previous positions. They see structure and agency as complementary forces – structure influences human behaviour, and humans are capable of changing the social structures they inhabit. Structuration issue one prominent example of this view.
The first approach (emphasizing the importance of societal structure) dominated in classical sociology.[citation needed] Theorists saw unique aspects of the social world that could not be explained simply by the sum of the individuals present. Durkheim strongly believed that the collective had emergent properties of its own and saw the need for a science which would deal with this emergence. The second approach (methodological individualism, etc.), however, also has a well-established position in social science. Many theorists still follow this course (economists, for example, tend to disregard any kind of holism).
The central debate, therefore, pits theorists committed to the notions of methodological holism against those committed to methodological individualism. The first notion, methodological holism, is the idea that actors are socialized and embedded into social structures and institutions that constrain, or enable, and generally shape the individuals' dispositions towards, and capacities for, action, and that this social structure should be taken as primary and most significant. The second notion, methodological individualism, is the idea that actors are the central theoretical and ontological elements in social systems, and social structure is an epiphenomenon, a result and consequence of the actions and activities of interacting individuals.
Major theorists
Georg Simmel
Georg Simmel (1858–1918) was one of the first generation of German nonpositivist sociologists. His studies pioneered the concepts of social structure and agency. His most famous works today include The Metropolis and Mental Life and The Philosophy of Money.
Norbert Elias
Norbert Elias (1897–1990) was a German sociologist whose work focused on the relationship between power, behaviour, emotion, and knowledge over time. He significantly shaped what is called process sociology or figurational sociology.
Talcott Parsons
Talcott Parsons (1902–1979) was an American sociologist and the main theorist of action theory (misleadingly called "structural functionalism") in sociology from the 1930s in the United States. His works analyze social structure but in terms of voluntary action and through patterns of normative institutionalization by codifying its theoretical gestalt into a system-theoretical framework based on the idea of living systems and cybernetic hierarchy. For Parsons there is no structure–agency problem. It is a pseudo-problem. His development of Max Weber's means-end action structure is summarized in Instrumental and value-rational action
Pierre Bourdieu
Pierre Bourdieu (1930–2002) was a French theorist who presented his theory of practice on the dichotomic understanding of the relation between agency and structure in a great number of publications, beginning with An Outline of the Theory of Practice in 1972, where he presented the concept of habitus.[citation needed] His book Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste (1979), was named as one of the 20th century's 10 most important works of sociology by the International Sociological Association.[3]
The key concepts in Bourdieu's work are habitus, field, and capital. The agent is socialized in a "field", an evolving set of roles and relationships in a social domain, where various forms of "capital" such as prestige or financial resources are at stake. As the agent accommodates to their roles and relationships in the context of their position in the field, they internalize relationships and expectations for operating in that domain. These internalized relationships and habitual expectations and relationships form, over time, the habitus.
Bourdieu's work attempts to reconcile structure and agency, as external structures are internalized into the habitus while the actions of the agent externalize interactions between actors into the social relationships in the field. Bourdieu's theory, therefore, is a dialectic between "externalizing the internal", and "internalizing the external".
Berger and Luckmann
Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann in their Social Construction of Reality (1966) saw the relationship between structure and agency as dialectical. Society forms the individuals who create society – forming a continuous loop.[5][verification needed]
James Coleman
The sociologist James Samuel Coleman famously diagramed the link between macrosociological phenomena and individual behaviour in what is commonly referred to as Coleman's Boat.[6] A macro-level phenomenon is described as instigating particular actions by individuals, which results in a subsequent macro-level phenomenon. In this way, individual action is taken in reference to a macro-sociological structure, and that action (by many individuals) results in change to that macro-structure.
Anthony Giddens
Contemporary sociology has generally aimed toward a reconciliation of structure and agency as concepts. Anthony Giddens has developed structuration theory in such works as The Constitution of Society (1984). He presents a developed attempt to move beyond the dualism of structure and agency and argues for the "duality of structure" – where social structure is both the medium and the outcome of social action, and agents and structures as mutually constitutive entities with "equal ontological status".[5] For Giddens, an agent's common interaction with structure, as a system of norms, is described as structuration. The term reflexivity is used to refer to the ability of an agent to consciously alter his or her place in the social structure; thus globalization and the emergence of the 'post-traditional' society might be said to allow for "greater social reflexivity". Social and political sciences are therefore important because social knowledge, as self-knowledge, is potentially emancipatory.[8][verification needed]
Klaus Hurrelmann
His access to research on structure and agency is characterized by socialization theory. Central to the theory is the life-long interaction between the individual and his/her longing for freedom and autonomy, and society with its pressure of order and structure. As he states in his "Model of Productive Processing of Reality (PPR)", personality "does not form independently from society any of its functions or dimensions but is continuously being shaped, in a concrete, historically conveyed life world, throughout the entire space of the life span". The PPR model places the human subject in a social and ecological context that must be absorbed and processed subjectively. The human being as an autonomous subject has the lifelong task to harmonize the processes of social integration and personal individualization. This task is mastered in specific steps that are typical for the respective age and the achieved developmental stage ("developmental tasks").
Roberto Unger
The social theorist and legal philosopher Roberto Mangabeira Unger developed the thesis of negative capability to address this problem of agency in relation to structure. In his work on false necessity – or anti-necessitarian social theory – Unger recognizes the constraints of structure and its molding influence upon the individual, but at the same time finds the individual able to resist, deny, and transcend their context. The varieties of this resistance are negative capability. Unlike other theories of structure and agency, negative capability does not reduce the individual to a simple actor possessing only the dual capacity of compliance or rebellion, but rather sees him or her as able to partake in a variety of activities of self empowerment.
Recent developments
A recent development in the debate is the critical realist structure/agency perspective embodied in Roy Bhaskar's transformational model of social action (TMSA) which he later expanded into his concept of four-planar social being. A major difference between Giddens' structuration theory and the TMSA is that the TMSA includes a temporal element (time). The TMSA has been further advocated and applied in other social science fields by additional authors, for example in economics by Tony Lawson and in sociology by Margaret Archer. In 2005, the Journal of Management Studies debated the merits of critical realism.
Kenneth Wilkinson in the Community in Rural America took an interactional/field theoretical perspective focusing on the role of community agency in contributing to the emergence of community.
With critical psychology as a framework, the Danish psychologist Ole Dreier proposes in his book Psychotherapy in Everyday Life that we may best conceptualize persons as participants in social practices (that constitute social structures) who can either reproduce or change these social practices. This indicates that neither participants, nor social practices can be understood when looked at in isolation (in fact, this undermines the very idea of trying to do so), since practice and structure is co-created by participants and since the participants can only be called so, if they participate in a social practice.[16]
The structure/agency debate continues to evolve, with contributions such as Nicos Mouzelis's Sociological Theory: What Went Wrong? and Margaret Archer's Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach continuing to push the ongoing development of structure/agency theory. Work in information systems by Mutch (2010) has emphasized Archer's Realist Social Theory as well as Robert Archer's (2018) application in the field of education policy[20] and organization theory.[21] In entrepreneurship a discussion between Sarason et al. and Mole & Mole (2010) used Archer's theory to critique structuration by arguing that starting a new business organization needs to be understood in the context of social structure and agency. However, this depends upon one's view of structure, which differs between Giddens and Archer. Hence if strata in social reality have different ontologies, then they must be viewed as a dualism. Moreover, agents have causal power, and ultimate concerns which they try to fallibly put into practice. Mole and Mole propose entrepreneurship as the study of the interplay between the structures of a society and the agents within it.
Purported differences in approach between European and American thinkers
|
This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (July 2009)
|
While the structure–agency debate has been a central issue in social theory, and recent theoretical reconciliation attempts have been made, structure–agency theory has tended to develop more in European countries by European theorists, while social theorists from the United States have tended to focus instead on the issue of integration between macrosociological and microsociological perspectives. George Ritzer examines these issues (and surveys the structure agency debate) in greater detail in his book Modern Sociological Theory (2000).
See also
References
Footnotes
- Barker 2005, p. 448.
- Bourdieu 1977; Bourdieu 1990; Hurrelmann 1988.
- Swartz 2004, pp. 360–361.
- Berger & Luckmann 1966.
- Jary & Jary 1995, pp. 664, 774.
- Stoltz, Dustin (25 January 2014). "Diagrams of Theory: Coleman's Boat". DustinStoltz.com. Dustin Stoltz. Retrieved 13 April 2018.
- Giddens 1984.
- Gauntlett 2002, pp. 93–96.
- Hurrelmann 1988, p. 42.
- Hurrelmann 1988.
- Lovin & Perry 1990; Unger 2004, p. 282.
- Bhaskar 2014.
- Bhaskar 2008.
- Contu & Willmott 2005; Reed 2005a; Reed 2005b.
- Wilkinson 1991.
- Dreier 2008, ch. 2.
- Mouzelis 1995.
- Archer 1995.
- Mutch 2010.
- Archer, Robert (2018). Education Policy and Realist Social Theory. doi:10.4324/9780203166536. ISBN 9781134493548.
- Archer, Robert (2000). "The Place of Culture in Organization Theory: Introducing the Morphogenetic Approach". Organization. 7 (1): 95–128. doi:10.1177/135050840071006. S2CID 145352259.
- Mole & Mole 2010.
- Ritzer 2000.
Bibliography
- Archer, Margaret S. (1995). Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511557675. ISBN 978-0-521-48176-2.
- Archer, Robert (2018). Education Policy and Realist Social Theory: Primary Teachers, Child-Centred Philosophy and the New Managerialism. London & New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203166536. ISBN 978-0-415-26839-4.
- Barker, Chris (2005). Cultural Studies: Theory and Practice. London: Sage. ISBN 978-0-7619-4156-9.
Cultural studies : theory and practice
Barker, Chris, 1955-
Read Book ">
- Berger, Peter L.; Luckmann, Thomas (1966). The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. Garden City, New York: Anchor Books. ISBN 978-0-385-05898-8.
- Bhaskar, Roy (2008). Dialectic: The Pulse of Freedom. London: Routledge.
- ——— (2014). The Possibility of Naturalism: A Philosophical Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences (4th ed.). London: Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-79889-2.
- Bourdieu, Pierre (1977). Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press (published 2013). doi:10.1017/CBO9780511812507. ISBN 978-0-511-81250-7.
- ——— (1990). The Logic of Practice. Cambridge, England: Polity Press.
- Contu, Alessia; Willmott, Hugh (2005). "You Spin Me Round: The Realist Turn in Organization and Management Studies". Journal of Management Studies. 42 (8): 1645–1662. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6486.2005.00560.x. ISSN 1467-6486.
- Dreier, Ole (2008). Psychotherapy in Everyday Life. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
- Gauntlett, David (2002). Media, Gender, and Identity: An Introduction. London: Routledge (published 2004). ISBN 978-0-415-18960-6.
Media, gender, and identity : an introduction
Gauntlett, David
Read Book ">
- Giddens, Anthony (1984). The Constitution of Society. Cambridge, England: Polity Press.
- Hurrelmann, Klaus (1988). Social Structure and Personality Development. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press (published 2009). ISBN 978-0-521-35747-0.
Social structure and personality development : the individual as a productive processor of reality
Hurrelmann, Klaus
Read Book ">
- Jary, David; Jary, Julia Jary (1995). Collins Dictionary of Sociology (2nd ed.). Glasgow: HarperCollins. ISBN 978-0-00-470804-1.
Collins dictionary of sociology
Jary, David
Read Book ">
- Lawson, Tony (1997). Economics and Reality. London: Routledge.
- Lovin, Robin W.; Perry, Michael J., eds. (1990). Critique and Construction: A Symposium on Roberto Unger's Politics. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
- Mole, Kevin F.; Mole, Miranda (2010). "Entrepreneurship as the Structuration of Individual and Opportunity: A Response Using a Critical Realist Perspective" (PDF). Journal of Business Venturing. 25 (2): 230–237. doi:10.1016/j.jbusvent.2008.06.002. ISSN 0883-9026.
- Mouzelis, Nicos (1995). Sociological Theory: What Went Wrong?. London: Routledge. ISBN 9780415076944.
Sociological theory : what went wrong? : diagnosis and remedies
Mouzelis, Nicos P
Read Book ">
- Mutch, Alistair (2010). "Technology, Organization, and Structure – A Morphogenetic Approach". Organization Science. 21 (2): 507–520. doi:10.1287/orsc.1090.0441. ISSN 1526-5455.
- Reed, Michael (2005a). "The Realist Turn in Organization and Management Studies". Journal of Management Studies. 42 (8): 1621–1644. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6486.2005.00559.x. ISSN 1467-6486.
- ——— (2005b). "Doing the Loco-Motion: Response to Contu and Willmott's Commentary on 'The Realist Turn in Organization and Management Studies'". Journal of Management Studies. 42 (8): 1663–1673. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6486.2005.00561.x. ISSN 1467-6486.
- Ritzer, George (2000). Modern Sociological Theory (5th ed.). Boston, Massachusetts: McGraw-Hill. ISBN 978-0-07-229604-4.
Modern sociological theory
Ritzer, George
Read Book ">
- Swartz, David L. (2004). "From Critical Sociology to Public Intellectual: Pierre Bourdieu & Politics". In Swartz, David L.; Zolberg, Vera L. (eds.). After Bourdieu: Influence, Critique, Elaboration. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer (published 2005). pp. 333–364. doi:10.1007/1-4020-2589-0_13. ISBN 978-1-4020-2589-1.
- Unger, Roberto Mangabeira (2004). False Necessity: Anti-Necessitarian Social Theory in the Service of Radical Democracy (rev. ed.). London: Verso. ISBN 978-1-85984-331-4.
False necessity--anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy : from Politics, a work in constructive social theory
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira
Read Book ">
- Wilkinson, Kenneth P. (1991). The Community in Rural America. Contributions in Sociology. Vol. 95. New York: Greenwood Press. ISBN 978-0-313-26467-2.
The community in rural America
Wilkinson, Kenneth P
Read Book ">
Further reading
- Archer, Margaret S. (2003). Structure, Agency and the Internal Conversation. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139087315. ISBN 978-1-139-08731-5.
- Bhaskar, Roy (1989). Reclaiming Reality. London: Verso. ISBN 9780860912378.
Reclaiming reality : a critical approach to contemporary philosophy
Bhaskar, Roy, 1944-
Read Book ">
- Bourdieu, Pierre; Wacquant, Loïc J. D. (1992). An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-06741-4.
An invitation to reflexive sociology
Bourdieu, Pierre, 1930-2002
Read Book ">
- Elias, Norbert (1978). What Is Sociology?. London: Hutchinson.
- Giddens, Anthony (1976). New Rules of Sociological Method.
- Giddens, Anthony (1976). New Rules of Sociological Method.
- Orlando, Vittorio; Conrad, Maximilian (2024). "Agency and structure in the age of European disintegration". Frontiers in Political Science. 6. doi:10.3389/fpos.2024.1383485.
- Turner, Jonathan H. (1991). The Structure of Sociological Theory (5th ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
- Unger, Roberto Mangabeira (1987). Social Theory: Its Situation and Its Task. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521329750.
False necessity--anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira
Read Book ">
Links
See Also
Subcategories``ёёё]]]
`0-9`A`B`C`D`E`F`G`H`I`J`K`L`M`N`O`P`Q`R`S`T`U`V`W`X`Y`Z
Index``ёёё]]]
``0-9``A``B``C``D``E``F``G``H``I``J``K``L``M``N``O``P``Q``R``S``T``U``V``W``X``Y``Z
Pages in Other Languages
Forking
Categories:
Categories:
Philosophy of social science
Sociological terminology
Sociological theories
Management cybernetics
Comments (0)
You don't have permission to comment on this page.